Kierkegaard and the Life of Faith: The Aesthetic, the Ethical, and the Religious in Fear and Trembling
“A thorough, considered, and provocative treatment of what justifiably remains Kierkegaard’s most famous book.” —Marginalia Review of Books

Soren Kierkegaard’s masterful work Fear and Trembling interrogates the story of Abraham and Isaac, finding there one of the most profound and critical dilemmas in all of religious philosophy. While several commentaries and critical editions exist, Jeffrey Hanson offers a distinctive approach to this crucial text.

Hanson gives equal weight to all three of Kierkegaard’s “problems,” dealing with Fear and Trembling as part of the entire corpus of Kierkegaard’s thought and putting all parts into relation with each other. Additionally, he offers a distinctive analysis of the Abraham story and other biblical texts, giving particular attention to questions of poetics, language, and philosophy, especially as each relates to the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious.

Presented in a thoughtful and fresh manner, Hanson’s claims are original and edifying. This new reading of Kierkegaard will stimulate fruitful dialogue on well-traveled philosophical ground.
"1123727819"
Kierkegaard and the Life of Faith: The Aesthetic, the Ethical, and the Religious in Fear and Trembling
“A thorough, considered, and provocative treatment of what justifiably remains Kierkegaard’s most famous book.” —Marginalia Review of Books

Soren Kierkegaard’s masterful work Fear and Trembling interrogates the story of Abraham and Isaac, finding there one of the most profound and critical dilemmas in all of religious philosophy. While several commentaries and critical editions exist, Jeffrey Hanson offers a distinctive approach to this crucial text.

Hanson gives equal weight to all three of Kierkegaard’s “problems,” dealing with Fear and Trembling as part of the entire corpus of Kierkegaard’s thought and putting all parts into relation with each other. Additionally, he offers a distinctive analysis of the Abraham story and other biblical texts, giving particular attention to questions of poetics, language, and philosophy, especially as each relates to the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious.

Presented in a thoughtful and fresh manner, Hanson’s claims are original and edifying. This new reading of Kierkegaard will stimulate fruitful dialogue on well-traveled philosophical ground.
13.49 In Stock
Kierkegaard and the Life of Faith: The Aesthetic, the Ethical, and the Religious in Fear and Trembling

Kierkegaard and the Life of Faith: The Aesthetic, the Ethical, and the Religious in Fear and Trembling

by Jeffrey Hanson
Kierkegaard and the Life of Faith: The Aesthetic, the Ethical, and the Religious in Fear and Trembling

Kierkegaard and the Life of Faith: The Aesthetic, the Ethical, and the Religious in Fear and Trembling

by Jeffrey Hanson

eBook

$13.49  $17.99 Save 25% Current price is $13.49, Original price is $17.99. You Save 25%.

Available on Compatible NOOK devices, the free NOOK App and in My Digital Library.
WANT A NOOK?  Explore Now

Related collections and offers

LEND ME® See Details

Overview

“A thorough, considered, and provocative treatment of what justifiably remains Kierkegaard’s most famous book.” —Marginalia Review of Books

Soren Kierkegaard’s masterful work Fear and Trembling interrogates the story of Abraham and Isaac, finding there one of the most profound and critical dilemmas in all of religious philosophy. While several commentaries and critical editions exist, Jeffrey Hanson offers a distinctive approach to this crucial text.

Hanson gives equal weight to all three of Kierkegaard’s “problems,” dealing with Fear and Trembling as part of the entire corpus of Kierkegaard’s thought and putting all parts into relation with each other. Additionally, he offers a distinctive analysis of the Abraham story and other biblical texts, giving particular attention to questions of poetics, language, and philosophy, especially as each relates to the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious.

Presented in a thoughtful and fresh manner, Hanson’s claims are original and edifying. This new reading of Kierkegaard will stimulate fruitful dialogue on well-traveled philosophical ground.

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780253025029
Publisher: Indiana University Press
Publication date: 12/22/2021
Series: Philosophy of Religion
Sold by: Barnes & Noble
Format: eBook
Pages: 261
File size: 693 KB
Age Range: 18 Years

About the Author

Jeffrey Hanson is Research Associate in the Program for Integrative Knowledge and Human Flourishing at Harvard University's Institute for Quantitative Social Science. He is editor of Kierkegaard as Phenomenologist: An Experiment and (with Michael R. Kelly) of Michel Henry: The Affects of Thought.

Read an Excerpt

Kierkegaard and the Life of Faith

The Aesthetic, the Ethical, and the Religious in Fear and Trembling


By Jeffrey Hanson

Indiana University Press

Copyright © 2017 Jeffrey Hanson
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-0-253-02502-9



CHAPTER 1

Titular Matters


It is no secret that the title "Fear and Trembling" comes from the letter of Saint Paul to the Philippians, chapter 2, verse 12. It is clearly meant to capture the pervasive mood of the text, as Kierkegaard himself approvingly noted in the review of it that was penned by Bishop Mynster. In that review, Mynster asked the question, "But why is that work called Fear and Trembling? Because its author has vividly comprehended, has deeply felt, has expressed with the full power of language the horror that must grip a person's soul when he is confronted by a task whose demands he dare not evade, and when his understanding is yet unable to disperse the appearance with its demand that seems to call him out from the eternal order to which every human being shall submit." In The Point of View for My Work as an Author, Kierkegaard wrote that he had been pleased to find that Mynster's remarks found the proper emphasis. So clearly part of the reason Kierkegaard chose this title was to create an atmospheric effect in the mind of the reader. It is meant to summon a mood of seriousness, of anxiety in the face of being called to an exceptional task, a task that cannot be explained in traditional philosophical terms. An examination of the chapter from Paul reveals other clear associations that also pervade the text. The context of verse 12 — which reads, "Wherefore, my beloved, as ye have always obeyed, not as in my presence only, but now much more in my absence, work out your own salvation with fear and trembling" — is immediately following one of the more important passages in Scripture for kenotic theological speculation, which is itself situated before and after exhortations by Paul to the distinctive moral life that the Philippian faithful should be living out. He calls them to have "the same love, being of one accord, of one mind"; he instructs them to "let nothing be done through strife or vainglory; but in lowliness of mind let each esteem other better than themselves"; and he encourages them to "look not every man on his own things, but every man also on the things of others." These moral directions find their justification in the kenotic passage; the Philippian believers are to act this way in order to model the mind of Christ: "Let this mind be in you, which was also in Christ Jesus: Who, being in the form of God, thought it not robbery to be equal with God: But made himself of no reputation, and took upon him the form of a servant, and was made in the likeness of men: And being found in fashion as a man, he humbled himself, and became obedient unto death, even the death of the cross."

The Philippians, then, are to be as Christ was; they are to imitate his humility, his adoption of a life of service, and his obedience to the Father, even if that obedience means submitting to the worst kind of death. Having done all this, Christ is exalted by God the Father and is given the name that is above all names. Thereafter, in verse 12 Paul instructs his hearers to work out their own salvation in imitation of Christ's kenotic self-emptying and (one presumes) in anticipation of sharing in his rewards. Less often noticed is the subsequent verse, which reads, "For it is God which worketh in you both to will and to do of his good pleasure." The faithful are to work out their salvation in fear and trembling because it is God who is working in them. The reference to Paul can be understood quite straightforwardly as a preliminary intimation of the text's intent to lay the foundation for a "second ethics," to suggest how the ethical ideal can be rejected and rereceived in altered fashion as a component of the life of faith.

The theme of Philippians 2 is one that is forever in the background of Fear and Trembling; as Christ emptied himself radically, so must the faithful believer empty herself and adopt a wholly transformed style of life, one inclusive of obedience to the will of the Father, humility, service to others, unity, and the setting aside of all self-interest and rivalry. Without making too much, then, of the connection between the content of Fear and Trembling and Philippians 2 we can easily say that they both take as their concern the morally significant ways in which the believer's life ought to be transformed by her faith. The believer is exhorted by both Paul and Kierkegaard to be conscious of the reality that it is God who works in her life to effectuate her conformity to Christ's moral model and that this work is done by God to capacitate her knowledge of, and ability to execute, his will. So not only is the particular verse an appropriate choice with respect to the atmosphere or mood of the text as a whole, so also the chapter's larger theme is one that echoes with the text's content as a whole.

The subtitle to Fear and Trembling, "Dialectical Lyric," has posed a challenge for commentators if only because no one knows what to make of it. It seems fairly obvious that Kierkegaard meant to refer to the form of the work, which he was elsewhere perfectly content to call "aesthetic," so clearly there is no conflict between the designation of "aesthetic" and the designation of "dialectical lyric"; and it seems equally obvious that the form of the work is meant to combine two seemingly incongruous genre descriptors. "Dialectic" suggests the methodical rigor of modernist discursive reason, while "lyric" suggests the stylistic elegance of poetry or song. It is undeniably the case that Kierkegaard intended that the work innovate in terms of its form, that it partake of philosophical rigor and beauty in expression, but much more than that is difficult to say, especially (and this may be the most salient point to note about the subtitle) since Kierkegaard never again had recourse to the term "dialectical lyric" and did not use it again in his published writings."

Certainly the term "lyric" in the subtitle has contributed to a common way of understanding who the text's author, Johannes de Silentio, is — namely, as a poet. Yet I wish to complicate matters because Silentio's status as a poet in a straightforward sense is far from clear, and calling him a poet leads to the dubious implication that his work is of a piece with the project of idealization, which is not his agenda at all but is part and parcel of resignation and the dead-end of unreconstructed aestheticizing. As scholars of this text know, on the original title page drafted for Fear and Trembling, Johannes de Silentio was billed as "a poetic person who exists only among poets." And scholars further know that Silentio denies that he is a philosopher. The combination of the two observations, as well as the lengthy meditation on the relationship between the poet and the hero found in the "Eulogy on Abraham," has led many to characterize Silentio as a poet; however, this is a highly problematic attribution for three reasons, in escalating order of importance.

First, Kierkegaard withdrew the original characterization of Silentio as a poetic person existing only among poets and presumably did so for a reason. The deliberate nature of this exclusion is underscored by the one-time presence in the preface of a description of Silentio as a "formerly poetic person." Second, there is no real reason to identify Silentio with the poet spoken of in the "Eulogy"; this has been repeatedly done because one could construe a parallelism between what Silentio says there and what he is currently undertaking in the text before us, but that Silentio thinks of himself as a poet or as "the poet" of the "Eulogy" remains an unwarranted assumption. This is especially so in view of the third reason, which is that every time Silentio introduces an illustrative narrative in the third Problema section he explicitly dissociates his use of the narrative vignette from poetic usage and always distinguishes between his own use of the narrative and the use that would be made of it by "poets."

This final observation will be developed at greater length in the chapter on Problema III, but suffice it say for now that I do not take the view that Silentio can be unproblematically viewed as a poet; in point of fact it is quite clear that he always distances himself from "the poets." This distancing was always part of the original plan for the text, as an outline of Fear and Trembling from the journals reveals. There Kierkegaard wrote, "If the present age had a poet he would be able to relate what these two men (Abraham and Isaac) talked about along the way," and again he asks, "Where indeed is the contemporary poet who has intimations of such conflicts? And yet Abraham's conduct was genuinely poetic, noble, more noble than anything I have read in tragedies. So even in germ, Fear and Trembling was intended to be "poetic" in a different, more genuine vein. It must first be taken into account that Silentio more often speaks of himself as not a poet than as one, and then, in the course of this work, I will develop a richer account of what sort of poetics Silentio is engaged in. To anticipate, let me point out that a clue is provided by Kierkegaard himself in an 1849 journal entry:

I understood myself to be what I must call a poet of the religious, not however that my personal life should express the opposite — no, I strive continually, but that I am a "poet" expresses that I do not confuse myself with the ideal.

My task was to cast Christianity into reflection, not poetically to idealize (for the essentially Christian, after all, is itself the ideal) but with poetic fervor to present the total ideality at its most ideal — always ending with: I am not that, but I strive. If the latter does not prove correct and is not true about me, then everything is cast in intellectual form and falls short.


Silentio could arguably be understood as a poet in the same sense that Kierkegaard thought of himself as a poet; in this connection, "poet" signifies principally one who recognizes oneself as not realizing the ideal. For Kierkegaard the man, writing in his journal, to be a poet means to recognize that one is not the ideal but that one strives for it. This part perhaps is not perfectly analogous, inasmuch as Silentio may not be actually striving for faith, but he does respect it and even is sometimes clearly impressed, not to say shattered, by it. But the comparison still holds for two principal reasons.

First, Silentio, like Kierkegaard himself, could be said to "cast Christianity into reflection." This is not the same as pretending to comprehend Christianity philosophically, something Silentio argues cannot be doned. It is to "shed light" indirectly or set off the phenomenon in question negatively, by contrast with what it is not, and this Silentio does quite frequently. Again in the journal, Kierkegaard says plainly of this pseudonym: "Johannes de Silentio has never claimed to be a believer; just the opposite, he has explained that he is not a believer — in order to illuminate faith negatively." It is quite clear from the text itself that Silentio is not a faithful person, and so from him we get an "outsider's perspective." There is in this some good to be had surely, as outsiders often see more clearly than insiders, but readers of Fear and Trembling also should be on guard against potential distortions in the account. It is my view that these are few and far between, and I will remark on them as they come up, but for the most part Silentio reports on faith accurately and sympathetically and only sometimes imperfectly, owing to his inability to know what only the faithful themselves could know. In one of his unpublished replies to Theophilus Nicolaus, Kierkegaard clarified Silentio's strategy as an effort "merely to illuminate Abraham, not to explain Abraham directly, for after all he cannot understand Abraham." Once again, this seems to speak to a distinction in Kierkegaard's mind between explaining the phenomenon at hand directly and indirectly casting light upon it, which seems to have been the aim of both his own authorial project and the small part of it that he attributed to Silentio.

Second, both Kierkegaard himself as an author and Silentio could be said to be at a remove from poetically idealizing; this too is distinguishable from what they are doing as writers and is not the same as casting into reflection. Kierkegaard writes in the entry above that the reason he is not poetically idealizing is because "the essentially Christian, after all, is itself the ideal." This is in fact another reason to question whether Silentio can be called a poet. An extremely important journal entry speaks on the connection between the poet and idealizing in these words: "What does it mean to poetize? It means to contribute ideality. The poet takes an actuality which lacks something of ideality and adds to it, and this is the poem." So if the poet is principally one who takes from actuality and idealizes it in order to create his poem, neither Kierkegaard nor Silentio can be a poet in the conventional sense because for both of them the actuality they take up in their examinations, the actuality they attempt to cast into reflection, is itself already the ideal. Kierkegaard calls himself a poet of the religious and says that he cannot be a straightforward poet, however, because the essentially Christian is already ideal. In the same journal entry, Kierkegaard ridicules Adam Oehlenschlager's attempt to poetize Socrates, because Socrates is already the ideal and cannot be poetized. The very attempt of a poet to idealize what is already actually ideal renders the poet a "laughingstock." In much the same way, Silentio aims to shed light on Abraham, but if Abraham is the true ideal of faith, then Abraham cannot be poetized any more than Socrates could be poetized. This must be kept in mind, particularly when reading the "Eulogy on Abraham" and particularly in order to keep an appropriate separation in place between Silentio's project and that of a conventional poet. It is of course true that like Kierkegaard himself Silentio brings "poetic fervor" to his work, but this does not make him a poet in a straightforward sense.

The obvious reference in the pseudonymous author of this text's name to silence must also be accounted for briefly here. The irony of our author's loquaciousness on faith and its apparent contrast to his own name has been noted, but fortunately there is not much in the way of mystery here with respect to the nature of silence. We have a clear sense of what Kierkegaard intended on this score from two sources: first, his own writing in the journal and Point of View, and, second, content internal to the text itself.

First, if we turn to Point of View, from the same passage where Kierkegaard hailed with approval Mynster's reaction to Fear and Trembling, we find these words: "I had made up my mind that I was a religious author whose concern is with the single individual, an idea (the single individual versus the public) in which a whole life- and worldview is concentrated. From now on, that is, as early as Fear and Trembling, the earnest observer who himself has religious presuppositions at his disposal, the earnest observer to whom one can make oneself understood at a distance and to whom one can speak in silence (the pseudonym: Johannes — de Silentio), became aware that this surely was a very singular kind of esthetic production.

So, most obviously the name "Silentio" signifies the intimate confidence enjoyed between friends who are able to communicate without words. Even in everyday language we often speak of wordless communication between persons as a mark of the depth of feeling and mutual understanding enjoyed by them, and quite simply, Kierkegaard intended the atmosphere of Fear and Trembling to be charged with this communicative ease. While the full case to be made on this score will be developed throughout the pages to come, a few passages from the journals and other writings can swiftly make the main point, which is that silence is not thought of by Kierkegaard or Silentio as incompatible with communication nor construed as an absence of content. In The Concept of Irony, for instance, Kierkegaard calls the "nothing" of mystical contemplation not an absence of content but asserts that it "is a nothing with regard to the representation, a nothing that is just as full of content as the silence of the night is full of sounds for someone who has ears to hear."

The clear meaning is that silence is not empty but full for one who can listen to silence properly. Similarly, in the journal Kierkegaard makes it clear that he distinguishes between a silence that is sheer absence of content or communication and a silence that is communicatively efficacious. He wrote in 1849: "'To be silent' means while reflecting to be able to speak, that is, about everything else imaginable, for otherwise it is conspicuous and suspicious for someone to be silent, and then it is not exactly silence, not complete silence. Kierkegaard calls silence "complete" when it is in fact precisely speaking, but speaking in an indirect manner, about everything except what the silence is about. By contrast silence is called "conspicuous" and by implication incomplete when it is mute. This description comports quite well with what I have sketched as the basics of Silentio's approach to his subject matter: though his name is "Silence" he speaks about faith only by talking around the point, illuminating by contrast, not speaking to something he understands directly.


(Continues...)

Excerpted from Kierkegaard and the Life of Faith by Jeffrey Hanson. Copyright © 2017 Jeffrey Hanson. Excerpted by permission of Indiana University Press.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Introduction
1. Titular Matters
2. A Philosophical Preface
3. A Narrative Approach
4. A Rhetorical Rehearsal
5. Beginning from the Heart
6. Teleological Suspensions
7. Absolute Duty
8. Silence and Speech
Conclusion
Notes
Index

What People are Saying About This

Professor Emeritus, Departments of Religion and Philosophy, Syracuse University - Edward F. Mooney

Hanson gives a nuanced and deeply informed reading of Kierkegaard’s pictures of religious faith as they are articulated in Fear and Trembling, perhaps the most arresting and complex work in the Dane’s authorship. Faith is linked to love and to gracefully weathering catastrophe, perhaps invisibly. There are only four or five books in English that dare focus entirely on this early masterpiece, and Hanson makes his mark as one of the best. Uniquely, he gives great attention to the second half of Fear and Trembling where Kierkegaard, or his pseudonym Johannes de Silentio, links faith to the tale of Agnes falling in love with the merman – a brilliant counterpoint to the notorious story of Abraham and Isaac. Best of all, Hanson pries faith free from dogma of any kind, and showsitto straddlethe ethicaland the aesthetic.

Professor Emeritus, Dept. of Philosophy, Univ. of New Mexico - Andrew Burgess

This book successfully challenges many recent approaches to Fear and Trembling, both for tending to treat that book in isolation from the rest of the Kierkegaardian canon and also for often focusing on an apparently intractable conflict between religion and ethics. Instead, drawing from Kierkegaardian remarks in The Concept of Anxiety, Hanson demonstrates how these books form two halves of a single argument, not only in terms of what The Concept of Anxiety calls a “second ethics,” but also in terms of a “second aesthetics.” Hanson’s interpretation thereby thrusts Fear and Trembling out from the sidelines and into the center of current debates about Kierkegaard’s authorship and helps it to illumine a wide range of other Kierkegaardian writings in new and unexpected ways.

author of Kierkegaard, Communication, and Virtue - Mark A. Tietjen

Jeffrey Hanson persuasively demonstrates that Fear and Trembling contains a variety of different styles, each of which colors the content being conveyed, and to the extent that we draw the connection between style and content, we gain an even stronger impression of the various arguments in Kierkegaard's best known book.

From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews