The Judge in a Democracy

The Judge in a Democracy

by Aharon Barak
The Judge in a Democracy

The Judge in a Democracy

by Aharon Barak

Paperback

$39.00 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM
    Qualifies for Free Shipping
  • PICK UP IN STORE
    Check Availability at Nearby Stores

Related collections and offers


Overview

Whether examining election outcomes, the legal status of terrorism suspects, or if (or how) people can be sentenced to death, a judge in a modern democracy assumes a role that raises some of the most contentious political issues of our day. But do judges even have a role beyond deciding the disputes before them under law? What are the criteria for judging the justices who write opinions for the United States Supreme Court or constitutional courts in other democracies? These are the questions that one of the world's foremost judges and legal theorists, Aharon Barak, poses in this book.


In fluent prose, Barak sets forth a powerful vision of the role of the judge. He argues that this role comprises two central elements beyond dispute resolution: bridging the gap between the law and society, and protecting the constitution and democracy. The former involves balancing the need to adapt the law to social change against the need for stability; the latter, judges' ultimate accountability, not to public opinion or to politicians, but to the "internal morality" of democracy.


Barak's vigorous support of "purposive interpretation" (interpreting legal texts—for example, statutes and constitutions—in light of their purpose) contrasts sharply with the influential "originalism" advocated by U.S. Supreme Court Justice Antonin Scalia.


As he explores these questions, Barak also traces how supreme courts in major democracies have evolved since World War II, and he guides us through many of his own decisions to show how he has tried to put these principles into action, even under the burden of judging on terrorism.


Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780691136158
Publisher: Princeton University Press
Publication date: 04/27/2008
Pages: 368
Sales rank: 1,058,621
Product dimensions: 6.00(w) x 9.25(h) x (d)

About the Author

Aharon Barak is President of the Supreme Court of Israel. He is the author of Judicial Discretion (1989), Purposive Interpretation in Law (Princeton, 2005), several books in Hebrew, and numerous articles in English-language law journals.

Read an Excerpt

The Judge in a Democracy


By Aharon Barak Princeton University Press
Copyright © 2006
Princeton University Press
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-691-13615-8


Chapter One BRIDGING THE GAP BETWEEN LAW AND SOCIETY

The law regulates relationships between people. It reflects the values of society. The role of the judge is to understand the purpose of law in society and to help the law achieve its purpose. But the law of a society is a living organism. It is based on a factual and social reality that is constantly changing. Sometimes the change is drastic and easily identifiable. Sometimes the change is minor and gradual, and cannot be noticed without the proper distance and perspective. Law's connection to this fluid reality implies that it too is always changing. Sometimes a change in the law precedes societal change and is even intended to stimulate it. In most cases, however, a change in the law is the result of a change in social reality. Indeed, when social reality changes, the law must change too. Just as change in social reality is the law of life, responsiveness to change in social reality is the life of the law.

These changes in the law, caused by changes in society, are sometimes appropriate and sufficient. The legal norm is flexible enough to reflect the change in reality naturally, without the need to change the norm and without creating a rift between law and reality. For example, the legal prohibition against possessing weapons works well, without the need for change, whetherthe weapon is an antique pistol or a sophisticated missile. Often, however, the legal norm is not flexible enough, and it fails to adapt to the new reality. A gap has formed between law and society. We need a new norm. For example, the norm that the owner of a carriage owes a duty of care to a pedestrian may be flexible enough to solve the problem of the duty of care that an automobile owner owes to a pedestrian. However, it is not flexible enough to solve the problem of industrialization, urbanization, and thousands of cars traveling on the streets, a situation in which proving negligence becomes more and more difficult. We need a change in law to move from negligence-based liability to strict liability in the context of an insurance regime. When changes occur in social reality, many of the old legal norms fail to adapt. The tort of negligence, which can generally deal with various changes in conventional risks, will likely prove insufficient to address an atomic risk. We would need a formal change in the norm itself.

The life of law is not just logic or experience. The life of law is renewal based on experience and logic, which adapt law to the new social reality. Indeed, there are always changes in law, caused by changes in society. The history of law is also the history of adapting law to life's changing needs. The legislative branch bears the primary role in making conscious changes in the law. It has the power to change the legislation that it itself created. It has the power to create new legal tools that can encompass the new social reality and even determine its nature and character. In the field of legislation, the legislature is the senior partner. The role of the judge is secondary and limited.

CHANGES IN LEGISLATION AND IN ITS INTERPRETATION

The judge has an important role in the legislative project: The judge interprets statutes. Statutes cannot be applied unless they are interpreted. The judge may give a statute a new meaning, a dynamic meaning, that seeks to bridge the gap between law and life's changing reality without changing the statute itself. The statute remains as it was, but its meaning changes, because the court has given it a new meaning that suits new social needs. The court fulfills its role as the junior partner in the legislative project. It realizes the judicial role by bridging the gap between law and life. I noted as much in a case that addressed, among other things, the question of whether Israel's civil procedure regulations recognized a class action lawsuit against the state. In answering in the affirmative, I noted:

We are concerned with the existing law, which must be given a new meaning. This is the classic role of the court. In doing so, it realizes one of its primary roles in a democracy, bridging the gap between law and life. The case before us is a simple example of the many situations in which an old tool does not fit a new reality, and the tool therefore must be given a new meaning, in order to address society's changing needs. It is no different from the many other situations in which courts today are prepared to give a dynamic meaning to old provisions, in order to adapt them to new needs.

Here is an additional example: Israeli tort law is based on the Tort Ordinance, passed at the end of the period of the British Mandate in Palestine (1947). According to the Ordinance, if an act of negligence causes a person's death, his dependents are entitled to compensation from the tortfeasor. The Tort Ordinance defines dependents to include "husband, wife, parents, and children." This provision was taken from the English statute, passed in 1846. There is no doubt that the British mandatory legislature intended to refer to a husband and wife who were lawfully married. However, what of the common law wife who has lived with her common law husband for many years and even given birth to a daughter with him? The common law husband becomes the victim of a deadly work-related accident; is the common law wife entitled to damages from the tortfeasor for loss of her dependency? When the question came before the Israeli Supreme Court, at a time when the phenomenon of common law marriages was prevalent, the Court answered in the affirmative. In my opinion, I wrote:

I am prepared to assume that the phrase "wife" in the 1846 English statute refers to a married woman. However, that does not mean that it is the meaning that an English court would give it today. It certainly does not mean that it is the meaning that we, in the State of Israel, would give the phrase "Husband, Wife." Much water has flowed through the English Thames and the Israeli Jordan since 1846. As judges in Israel, our duty is to give the phrase "Husband, Wife" the meaning assigned to it in Israeli society, and not in English Victorian society of the mid-nineteenth century ... that is mandated by our interpretive rules.

Here is an additional example from public law: The Defense Regulations (State of Emergency) enacted in 1945 by the British government continue to apply in Israel. Among other things, these regulations establish military censorship of publications in Israel. The military censor is authorized to ban publications that it deems likely to harm state security, public security, or the public peace. The Supreme Court has given this provision a dynamic interpretation, based on the fundamental principles of Israeli law. In my opinion, I noted that

The meaning that should be given to the Defense Regulations in the State of Israel is not identical to the meaning that they might have taken on during the period of the Mandate. Today, the Defense Regulations are part of the laws of a democratic state. They must be interpreted against the background of the fundamental principles of the Israeli legal system.

We held that the military censor may prevent publication only if the uncensored publication would create a near certainty of grave harm to state security, public security, or public peace.

Characteristic of these examples and many others is the change that has taken place in the law without any change occurring in the language of the legislation. Such a change is made possible by the change in the court's interpretation. It is made possible by the court's recognition of its role to bridge the gap created between the old statute and the new social reality. The court did not say, "Adapting the law to the new reality is not my role. It is the role of the legislature. If the legislature does not do anything, it bears the responsibility." The court viewed it as its own responsibility- complementary to the responsibility of the legislature-to give the old law a new meaning that suited the social needs of modern Israel.

Statutory interpretation will facilitate the statute's adaptation to changes in the conditions of existence only if the system of interpretation allows for that. Such a system is the system of purposive interpretation. It is predicated on giving a dynamic interpretation to the statute, to allow it to fulfill its design. In one case, I addressed the way in which dynamic interpretation works:

The meaning that should be given to a phrase in a statute is not fixed for eternity. The statute is part of life, and life changes. Understanding of the statute changes with changes in reality. The language of the statute remains as it was, but the meaning changes along with "changing life conditions" ... the statute integrates into the new reality. This is how an old statute speaks to the modern person. This is the source of the interpretive approach that "the statute always speaks" ... interpretation is a regenerative process. Old language should be filled with modern content, in order to minimize the gap between law and life. It is therefore correct to say, as Radbruch does, that the interpreter may understand the statute better than the author of the statute, and that the statute is always wiser than its creator ... the statute is a living creature; its interpretation must be dynamic. It must be understood in a way that integrates and advances modern reality.

Of course, it is not always possible to bridge the gap between law and life by giving a new and modern meaning to an old statute. Sometimes the judge lacks the power to bridge the gap between the old language of the statute and society's new reality. In such a case the judge must set aside his work tools. The judge may not act against the law. He can only hope that the legislature will do its job and repeal the old statute. The judge, as a faithful interpreter, cannot achieve such a result. For example, the court could not entirely repeal the military censorship of publications or, for that matter, civilian censorship of plays and movies, also created by the British mandatory regime. Such repeal required legislative intervention. Indeed, following a decision by the Supreme Court restricting civilian censorship, the legislature repealed censorship of plays. Censorship of movies, like military censorship, still exists. The judge lacks the power to deliver that change.

In this context, Guido Calabresi's proposition is noteworthy. He suggested that courts should be able to repeal legislation that has become obsolete. Of course, Calabresi's proposition cannot be implemented unless the legislature explicitly authorizes courts to repeal obsolete legislation. I personally do not think that is the proper solution to a painful problem. The right way is not to rely on judges to repeal obsolete laws but rather for the legislature to do so. Indeed, the Israeli legislature occasionally collects pieces of old legislation that are no longer necessary and repeals them. That is the right way to proceed.

CHANGES IN SOCIETY AFFECTING THE CONSTITUTIONALITY OF STATUTES

Social changes sometimes lead to a situation in which a statute passed in the context of a certain reality and that was constitutional at the time of its enactment becomes unconstitutional in light of a new social reality. Of course, the court will do everything it can to give the old statute a new meaning, in order to preserve its constitutionality. The limitations of interpretation, however, do not always allow that to happen. Where interpretation fails to give an old law a new meaning, the question may arise as to whether, in light of the social changes, the old statute is constitutional. Even though the court is not authorized to give a new meaning to an old statute, if such meaning deviates from the system's rules of interpretation, the court may declare the old statute, with the old meaning, unconstitutional. As an example, in 1986 the United States Supreme Court held that a statute criminalizing consensual homosexual relations between adults was constitutional. Twenty years passed. The United States Supreme Court overturned its prior holding. It held that the Constitution bars legislation criminalizing consensual sexual relations between adults. The difference between the two decisions did not reflect a constitutional change that took place during that period. Rather, the change that occurred was in American society, which learned to recognize the nature of homosexual relationships and was prepared to treat them with tolerance. Justice D. Dorner of the Israeli Supreme Court discussed this social change in a case that raised the issue of employee benefits for same-sex partners:

In the past, intimate relations between members of the same sex-relations considered to be a sin by monotheistic religions-were a criminal offense ... this treatment has gradually changed. Legal scholars have criticized the definition of a homosexual relationship as criminal and discrimination against homosexuals in all areas of life ... movements fighting for equal rights for homosexuals have sprung up. Today, the trend-which began in the 1970s-is to a liberal treatment of a person's sexual tendencies, which are viewed as a private matter.... Israeli law concerning homosexuals reflects the social changes that have taken place over the years.

CHANGES IN THE COMMON LAW

The court may not repeal an obsolete statute. It may, however, repeal a common law holding that has become obsolete. It may change even a non-obsolete precedent if it does not suit today's social needs. Indeed, judges created the common law. In doing so, they sought to provide a solution to the social needs of their time. As these needs change, judges must consider whether it is appropriate to change the judicial precedent itself, by expanding or restricting the existing case law or overturning an old precedent. Sometimes the new social reality necessitates creating new case law to resolve problems that did not arise at all in the past, where the goal of the new case law is to bridge the gap between law and the new social reality. Justice Agranat expressed this idea well:

Where a judge is presented with a set of facts based in new life conditions, for which the current law was not designed, the judge should review anew the logical premise on which the case law, created in a different background, is based. The goal is to adapt the case law to the new conditions, either by expanding or restricting it, or, where there is no other way, completely to abandon the logical premise which served as the basis for the existing law and to replace it with a different legal norm-even if the legal norm was previously unknown.

Within the common law project, the judge is the senior partner. The judge creates the common law and bears responsibility for making sure that it fulfills its role properly. The legislature is the junior partner, the outside observer, who generally intervenes only when asked to correct a particular issue or replace the entire legal regime from a common law regime to a statutory regime.

CHANGE AND STABILITY

The Dilemma of Change

The need for change presents the judge with a difficult dilemma, because change sometimes harms security, certainty, and stability. The judge must balance the need for change with the need for stability. Professor Roscoe Pound expressed this well more than eighty years ago: "Hence all thinking about law has struggled to reconcile the conflicting demands of the need of stability and of the need of change. Law must be stable and yet it cannot stand still."

(Continues...)



Excerpted from The Judge in a Democracy by Aharon Barak
Copyright © 2006 by Princeton University Press. Excerpted by permission.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Introduction ix

PART ONE: THE ROLE OF THE JUDGE 1

Chapter One: Bridging the Gap between Law and Society 3

Law and Society 3

Changes in Legislation and in Its Interpretation 4

Changes in Society Affecting the Constitutionality of Statutes 8

Changes in the Common Law 10

Change and Stability 11

Chapter Two: Protecting the Constitution and Democracy 20

The Struggle for Democracy 20

What Is Democracy? 23

The Separation of Powers 35

Democracy and the Rule of Law 51

Fundamental Principles 57

Independence of the Judiciary 76

Human Rights 81

Criticism and Response 88

PART TWO: THE MEANS OF REALIZING THE JUDICIAL ROLE 99

Chapter Three: Preconditions for Realizing the Judicial Role 101

Judicial Impartiality and Objectivity 101

Social Consensus 107

Public Confidence 109

Chapter Four: The Meaning of Means 113

The Legitimacy of the Means 113

Operative Legal Theory 113

Judicial Philosophy 116

Chapter Five: Interpretation 122

The Essence of Interpretation 122

Purposive Interpretation 125

Purposive Interpretation of a Constitution 127

Purposive Interpretation of Statutes 136

Purposive Interpretation and Judicial Discretion 146

Purposive Interpretation and Intentionalism
(or Subjective Purpose) 148

Purposive Interpretation and Old Textualism 149

Purposive Interpretation and New Textualism 152

Chapter Six: The Development of the Common Law 155

The Common Law as Judge-Made Law 155

Judicial Lawmaking 157

Overruling Precedent 158

Chapter Seven: Balancing and Weighing 164

The Centrality of Balancing and Weighing 164

Balancing and Categorization 166

The Nature of Balancing 167

Types of Balancing 170

The Advantages of Balancing 172

Critique of Balancing and Response 174

The Scope of the Balancing 175

Chapter Eight: Non-Justiciability, or "Political Questions" 177

The Role and Limits of Justiciability 177

Types of Justiciability 178

Justiciability and Public Confidence 186

Chapter Nine: Standing 190

Standing and Adjudication 190

Standing and Substantive Democracy 194

Chapter Ten: Comparative Law 197

The Importance of Comparative Law 197

The Influence of Comparative Law 198

Comparative Law and Interpretation of Statutes 199

Comparative Law and Interpretation of the Constitution 200

Use of Comparative Law in Practice 202

Chapter Eleven: The Judgment 205

Formulating the Judgment and Realizing the Judicial Role 205

The Judge as Part of the Panel 208

PART THREE: THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THE COURT AND THE OTHER BRANCHES OF THE STATE 213

Chapter Twelve: Tension among the Branches 215

Constant Tension 215

The Tension Is Natural and Desirable 216

The Attitude toward the State 217

Public Officials as Trustees 220

Duties of the Individual toward the State 222

Chapter Thirteen: The Relationship between the Judiciary and the Legislature 226

The Uniqueness of the Legislature 226

Judicial Review of Legislation 229

Judicial Review of Nonlegislative Decisions of the Legislature 231

The Dialogue between the Judiciary and the Legislature 236

Chapter Fourteen: The Relationship between the Judiciary and the Executive 241

The Scope of Review 241

Judicial Interpretation and Executive Interpretation 246

Executive Reasonableness 248

Proportionality 254

PART FOUR: EVALUATION OF THE ROLE OF A JUDGE IN A DEMOCRACY 261

Chapter Fifteen: Activism and Self-Restraint 263

Definition of the Terms 263

Some Definitions and Their Critiques 267

Definition of Activism and Self-Restraint 270

The Desirability of Activism or Self-Restraint 279

Chapter Sixteen: The Judicial Role and the Problem of Terrorism 283

Terrorism and Democracy 283

In Battle, the Laws Are Not Silent 287

The Balance between National Security and Human Rights 291

Scope of Judicial Review 298

Chapter Seventeen: The Role of the Judge: Theory, Practice, and the Future 306

Theory 306

Reality 310

The Future 310

Index 317

What People are Saying About This

Hanoch Dagan

This book provides a candid and elaborate account by a leading supreme court justice on his craft of judging. Aharon Barak discusses some of the most important (and controversial) jurisprudential questions and demonstrates the ways in which he has put his convictions on these matters into action in shaping Israeli jurisprudence. As such, The Judge represents a valuable encounter of legal theory and judicial practice. Judges and scholars associated with new constitutional courts will find the book instructive. American judges and scholars, in turn, will see it as a powerful antithesis to the approach of another prominent jurist, Justice Antonin Scalia of the United States Supreme Court.
Hanoch Dagan, Tel-Aviv University Faculty of Law School, author of "The Law and Ethics of Restitution"

Frank Iacobucci

A remarkable work by a remarkable jurist. A most important contribution to our understanding of the role of a judiciary in a democracy, this book will be of wide appeal to judges, legal scholars, and law students, as well as political theorists and others interested in the law and legal institutions.
Frank Iacobucci, retired Justice of the Supreme Court of Canada

Laurence Tribe

This book offers a plethora of intriguing examples of practical reason in the service of an eclectic mix of justice ethically conceived and of law as a body of rules and principles that bind us even when power is lacking to enforce those norms. Few jurists in the world have regularly confronted the kinds of seemingly impossible conundrums that Barak has with amazing frequency managed to turn into surprisingly agreeable outcomes.
Laurence Tribe, Harvard University, author of "American Constitutional Law"

From the Publisher

"This book offers a plethora of intriguing examples of practical reason in the service of an eclectic mix of justice ethically conceived and of law as a body of rules and principles that bind us even when power is lacking to enforce those norms. Few jurists in the world have regularly confronted the kinds of seemingly impossible conundrums that Barak has with amazing frequency managed to turn into surprisingly agreeable outcomes."—Laurence Tribe, Harvard University, author of American Constitutional Law

"A remarkable work by a remarkable jurist. A most important contribution to our understanding of the role of a judiciary in a democracy, this book will be of wide appeal to judges, legal scholars, and law students, as well as political theorists and others interested in the law and legal institutions."—Frank Iacobucci, retired Justice of the Supreme Court of Canada

"This book provides a candid and elaborate account by a leading supreme court justice on his craft of judging. Aharon Barak discusses some of the most important (and controversial) jurisprudential questions and demonstrates the ways in which he has put his convictions on these matters into action in shaping Israeli jurisprudence. As such, The Judge represents a valuable encounter of legal theory and judicial practice. Judges and scholars associated with new constitutional courts will find the book instructive. American judges and scholars, in turn, will see it as a powerful antithesis to the approach of another prominent jurist, Justice Antonin Scalia of the United States Supreme Court."—Hanoch Dagan, Tel-Aviv University Faculty of Law School, author of The Law and Ethics of Restitution

From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews